On choice-offering imperatives
نویسنده
چکیده
The law of propositional logic that states the deducibility of either A or B from A is not valid for imperatives (Ross’s paradox, cf. [9]). The command (or request, advice, etc.) in (1a) does not imply (1a) (unless it is taken in its alternative-presenting sense), otherwise when told the former, I would be justified in burning the letter rather then posting it. (1) a. Post this letter! 6⇒ b. Post this letter or burn it! Intuitively the most natural interpretation of the second imperative is as one presenting a choice between two actions. Following [2] (and [6]) I call these choice-offering imperatives. Another example of a choice-offering imperative is (2) with an occurence of Free Choice ‘any’ which, interestingly, is licensed in this context. (2) Take any card! Like (1a), this imperative should be interpreted as carrying with it a permission that explicates the fact that a choice is being offered. Possibility statements behave similarly (see [8]). Sentence (3b) has a reading under which it cannot be deduced from (3a), and ‘any’ is licensed in (4). (3) a. You may post this letter. 6⇒ b. You may post this letter or burn it. (4) You may take any card. In [1] I presented an analysis of modal expressions which explains the phenomena in (3) and (4). That analysis maintains a standard treatment of ‘or’ as logical disjunction (contra [11]) and a Kadmon & Landman style analysis of ‘any’ as existential quantifier (contra [3] and [4]) assuming, however, an independently motivated ‘Hamblin analysis’ for ∨ and ∃ as introducing sets of alternative propositions. Modal expressions are treated as operators over sets of propositional alternatives. In this way, since their interpretation can depend on the alternatives introduced by ‘or’ (∨) or ‘any’ (∃) in their scope, we can account for the free choice effect which arises in sentences like (3b) or (4). In this article I would like to extend this analysis to imperatives. The resulting theory will allow a unified account of the phenomena in (1)-(4). We will start by presenting our ‘alternative’ analysis for indefinites and disjunction.
منابع مشابه
A Semantics for Imperatives
Imperatives like ‘Post this letter or burn it!’ or ‘Take any card!’ are most naturally interpreted as presenting a choice between different alternatives. The article proposes an account of choice-offering imperatives and of their non-standard logical properties based on the framework of inquisitive semantics.
متن کاملUtility and implicatures of imperatives
The article defines the relevance or utility of an imperative in terms of how far it can help in increasing the probability of the occurrence of a desirable future world. In terms of this notion, we account for (i) the potential of imperatives to license free choice any in their scope; and (ii) the free choice effects of disjunctive and any-imperatives. 1 Choice-offering imperatives 1.1 Or in i...
متن کاملFree choice , modals , and imperatives
The article proposes an analysis of imperatives and possibility and necessity statements that (i) explains their differences with respect to the licensing of free choice any and (ii) accounts for the related phenomena of free choice disjunction in imperatives, permissions, and other possibility statements. Any and or are analyzed as operators introducing sets of alternative propositions. Free c...
متن کاملA logical account of free choice imperatives⇤
Since Ross’s observation that the instruction Post this letter does not entail Post this letter or burn it, imperatives have constituted a challenge for the logician. Building on ideas from inquisitive semantics, we propose an account in which imperatives are regarded as partial specifications of a set of options. We show that this account avoids Ross’s paradox and gives rise to a sensible noti...
متن کاملPermission and Choice
When it comes to permission imperatives, a basic question that must be answered is whether they should receive the same basic analysis as strong imperatives (i.e., those which express commands and the like). If the answer is positive, the difference should lie in some aspect of the context. Portner (2004, 2008), Schwager (2005b), and maybe Mastop (2005) take this view. If it is negative, a perm...
متن کامل